AFTER TWO YEARS With this issue Worldview completes two years of publication, and it seems a good time to pause and examine the journal's purpose, direction and future plans. This is “a journal of religion and international affairs.” An editorial in its first number announced that Worldview would be concerned with the broad area of ethics and foreign policy “as a baffling and heart-breaking problem, not an accomplish- # ment. At all times, among all nations, a tension between ethics and foreign policy seems inevi- table. In the world of 1958, when thermonuclear weapons have brought a new dimension of de- struction into history, the tension is infinitely heightened. Worldview will seek to explore the implications of this fact.” The tensions, of course, are no nearer “solution” now than they were two years ago, and anyone who has looked to this journal for ready answers must surely have been disappointed. What World- view has tried to do is to discover the problems and to provide a forum for the exchange of ideas. And it Ecteves that here it does not merely dupli- cate the efforts of other magazines. There are, for example, other journals that are concerned, week by week and month by month, with questions of religion and international affairs. One thinks of Christianity and Crisis and The Commonweal, or of America and The Christian Century. But these publications are written and edited from a specifically Protestant or a Catholic point of view. Worldview is “interfaith” in the mamost genuine sense of the term and thus provides ®mecting place for writers from the various re- ligious traditions. This is its special function, and Because of it the journal should be able to make # unique contribution toward the clarification of problems that are common to us all, and which femand whatever illumination the various reli- pous traditions can bring to them. We share a fmmon fate, and our best hope lies in the sharing our insights. worldview A JOURNAL OF RELIGION AND INTERNATIONAL AFFAIRS We hope that in its first two years this magazine has begun a process of intellectual exchange, of dialogue, which can be steadily deepened. We hope also that its range, both of writers and of readers, can be significantly expanded. A publi- cation like Worldview can never hope (indeed, should never hope, if it is to maintain its character) to reach a mass audience or directly to influence popular opinion. But it can be of (perhaps great) value to that smaller audience which is gs 4 concerned, either personally or professionally, wi the issues of ethics, security and survival in the modern world. It is for this audience that World- view is written and edited; it is to this audience that the journal must look for its influence and future. As we enter the decade of the 1960's it seems clear that the post-war period has finally ended and that an era of new perils, and new possibilities, is about to begin. The world continues to hover on the brink of nuclear suicide and the moral chal- lenge of disarmament must continue to haunt us, but it seems less likely now than in the past ten. years that the two super-powers will choose to solve their rivalry through the ultimate folly of war. What seems likely is that we are moving into an era of fierce economic and political competi- tion, a time when both the United States and the Soviet Union will turn their major attention to the underdeveloped areas of Asia and Africa, to prob- lems of the world’s exploding population and the measures needed to secure it from starvation and disease and death. The insights and imperatives of religion must not be absent from this coming era, or irrelevant to it. The forces of materialism and cynicism must not be the only ones which shape this world. As Worldview, in the new decade, begins its third year of publication, it will hope to provide a con- tinually more important forum where men of di- vergent views, but of common concerns, can meet to examine the great ethical challenges of their time and place. volume 2 number 12 3 | JECEMBE) J in the magazines The November issues of Current History and Com- mentary both contain articles by Hans J. Morgenthau on the subject of Soviet foreign policy. In these articles, Mr. Morgenthau makes the point that the foreign policy of Nikita Khrushchev represents a radical break with the past. “Much less a doctrinaire Communist than his predecessors, he has set out to accomplish the world-wide triumph of Communism, not as the heir of Marx and Lenin, but as the pragmatic competitor of the United States. He has set out to do what Lenin and Stalin never at- tempted: to defeat the foremost capitalist nation at its own gamie of technological and productive achievements.” Mr. Morgenthau describes Khrush- chev’s “new imperialism” as having three distinct motives. “[Khrushchev] offers the Soviet Union to the other nations of the world as a model to emulate, and especially to those who are underdeveloped and uncommitted. He seeks to spread the influence of the Soviet Union through foreign aid and trade. By overtaking the United States in technological and roductive achievements, he aims to reduce the United States to the status of a second-rank power.” These goals, Mr. Morgenthau suggests, are what lie behind the Soviet Premier’s repeated—and admit- tedly sincére—pleas for a relaxation of political and military tensions. But he insists that “‘the end to the Cold War’ in Khrushchev’s terminology amounts really to the conduct of the Cold War on Soviet terms. For as long as the non-Communist world remains able and willing to put up resistance to the professed Soviet aim to take over the world, the Cold War must go on.” In its winter issue, Cross Currents publishes a translation of a report on “Christians and the Preven- tion of War in the Atomic Age.” The report is the result of “an ecumenical inquiry” by a sub-committee of the Ecumenical Studies Commission of the French Protestant Federation. Proposed for general stud by the Federation, the report addresses the fol- lowing four questions: (1) the theological foun- dations for the Christian attitude to war, (2) the ethical problems of the participation of Christians in war, (3) the novel menace of the current situa- tion, and (4) the role of the ee oy The rt begins by remindin istians that “all nities and conflict issue forth from .. . the troubled depths of fallen man,” and that the re- pentance to which the Gospel recalls us compels us today ‘to “redefine the responsibilities of Christians in regard both to their own nations and to all man- kind.” The Christian response to the demands of the 2 both the Law of God and “the State must autonomy of politics.” Churches must “replace the fine old appeals to submission [to “the authorities”] and the simplist appeals to revolt with a — to guide Christians over difficult paths where must walk as adult citizens of a modern state.” The ethical problem of war involves Christians in the dangers of a “double morality.” As the authors of the report write: “Every war poses in the same terms the ethical problem of the conflicts of moralities . . . Culpable before God whatever you do, Christian, will you be objector or soldier?” But the authors see quite clearly that modern war is likely to be different in kind from every war of the past, and that the totality of the nuclear threat has made appeals to “patriotism” indefensible. “It is not enough to preach ‘Render to Caesar . . .’ when no one knows very well any longer who Caesar is. It is not enough to recall that the State has the duty of protecting society against . . . attacks . . . when the least spark risks causing a world conflagration.” Faced with these problems, the Churches can best discharge their responsibilities by means of a “political preaching.” “In the troubled and complex world of today, owe their members a constant aid, a political ‘care of souls’ which would keep in mind the great affirma- tions of the Gospel and international reality.” “What the Americans fail to realize,” write the editors of The Spectator by way of introducing an article on Spain, “is that when they accept Franco's oe at they must give him money or there ill be a Communist Spain, they are not in fact choosing either Franco or the Communists: they are choosing Franco and the Communists.” The article “Francos Spain” is by Ian Gilmour and appears in the issue of November 13. A lengthy analytical report which covers every feature of the Spanish dictator- ship, it should be of great interest to Americans, especially—as the editors suggest—the authors of the next Mutual Security Program. Also current and worthy of note: “Soviet-Chinese Relations” by Klaus Mehnert, In- ternational Affairs, October. “NATO, the Bomb and Socialism” by Peter Sedg- wick, Universities and Left Review, Autumn. “Moral Rearmament: the Answer to Communism?” by Robert A. Graham, S. J., America, November 2. PAMPHILUS I t t t r a BS BR THE POWER TO NEGOTIATE Our Approach Should Be from the Standpoint of Vital National Interest E. Raymond Platig The Cold War objectives of both the United States and the Soviet Union are basic factors in any possible negotiation of differences. A third, perhaps more tangible, factor is the distribution of power between the two blocs. Ever since Sputnik I took to space there has been much speculation concerning the relative power positions of the Communist powers and the West. One immediate but not too well-defined reaction to Sputnik I was that we ought to get down to serious negotiations with the Soviet Union immediately, since we seemed to have lost the race for military power. This approach to foreign policy is as dan- gerous as that of the crusading moralist. For the proposition which lies behind this position is that we can successfully negotiate with the Soviets from weakness. Successful negotiation from a position of weakness can be contemplated only if the nation with whom you are negotiating can be assumed to be magnanimous enough to grant you those minimum interest objectives you seek even though you do not have the power to demand them. It seems obvious that the present Soviet leaders are not capable of such magnanimity. (This initial panic response has by now pretty much passed, though one wonders if it is not still present in the attitude of an Administration which seems more concerned with the cost of armaments than with the need for armaments. ) Most observers today seem to be in agreement that we have not yet lost the race for military power but are in some danger of losing it. Observers dis- agree as to how much national effort is required in what length of time to assure that we do not lose the military race. It is somewhat disturbing to note that a great many observers not committed to a defense of the Administration’s actions are highly critical of those actions on the grounds that we are doing too little, not fast enough. Be that as it may, it seems Mr. Platig is a staff member of the Social Science Foundation and Associate Professor of International Relations in the University of Denver. The first part of his article was published last month. to me that the most accurate description which can be given to the present distribution of power be- tween the blocs is to say that we have a balance of uncertainty. The scales in which statesmen and analysts weigh relative national power are never delicate instru- ments, and the weights which they put into the scales are never clearly marked. This constitutional uncertainty of the whole process of power calcula- tion is exacerbated today by the uncertainty of the weights to be assigned to the rapidly developing weapons systems of modern military technology. The margin of possible error in current power cal- culations is thus quite large, large enough to make it unlikely that either side would commit itself to a policy which required a clear superiority of power. Thus we have the balance of uncertainty, a balance which may well continue for many many years. On the other hand, one cannot discount the possibility that the balance may be completely upset by some spectacular breakthrough in military technology by one side or the other, or by some decisive victory in the non-military aspects of the Cold War. In any event, there are only three conceivable positions of power from which we might negotiate. One is a position of weakness, another a position of balance, and the third a position of strength. I have already indicated my belief that we cannot expect to have satisfactory negotiations if we find ourselves in a position of weakness. It is tempting to think that if we found ourselves in a position of strength we would still be willing to negotiate and that indeed we would display that magnanimity toward the vital interests of the Communist states which we cannot anticipate that they would display toward us. I would like to think that this is true. However, our own tendency to adhere to a crusading moralism and our lack of success in bringing about successful negotiations in the period when we had a clear superiority of military strength do not en- courage this hope. It would appear, then, that the distribution of power which would be most conducive 3 to successful negotiation would be a distribution which puts the two sides essentially in balance, even though that balance may be a balance of uncer- tainty and a balance of terror. It should be evident from what we have said that the one configuration of these three factors which would be most conducive to a negotiated settlement of the Cold War is as follows. First, the attitude of the United States would have to be a non-crusading, non-moralistic one that would permit the nation to pursue only those limited objectives which would clearly serve to assure the survival and reasonable well-being of the United States. Two, the attitude of the Soviet Union toward the Cold War would also have to be one which led it to pursue a policy of objectives limited by a concern for its vital in- terests. The same can be said for other Communist states, especially Red China. Three, the distribution of power between the blocs would have to be one of essential balance. At the present time it is clear that the only one of these conditions which is met is the last one; that is, we are in a position of essential balance, although I must admit that I for one would feel a little more easy if the balance were a bit more clearly uncer- tain in our favor. My interpretation of Soviet ob- jectives, as I have already indicated, is that they are not limited solely by a concern for the vital national interests of the Soviet state, and this is a highly dis- couraging aspect of the present situation. We have, however, much more control over Ameri- can objectives than we do over Soviet objectives and it is in this area that I think we most need to straighten out our thinking in order to prepare for the time when—assuming Soviet objectives do change —it will be feasible to enter into serious negotiations. There is, however, more to be gained from this process of defining American vital interests and deciding upon the objectives which will serve them than merely being prepared to negotiate at some future date with the Soviets. It seems to me that by the very fact of our engaging in such a process we would do a great deal to put pressure upon the Soviets to change their objectives, and also to make the balance of uncertainty less uncertain in our favor. If I am correct that vital national interests provide a level of discourse which is universally apprehended and understood, then I think it follows that we would find ourselves for the first time speaking to the world’s statesmen and peoples in terms that they could understand. It is no secret that today Ameri- 4 can motives are much suspect in a large part of the world. Part of this suspicion can be laid to Soviet propaganda, but still a larger part of it can, I be- lieve, be traced to the fact that the uncommitted nations and peoples of the world, and even our allies, are highly reluctant to be involved in a great Ameri- can crusade which they see, and I think rightly, as ending in nuclear holocaust. If we could make it clear to these people that our objectives were limited, that we were willing to settle the Cold War on terms that would respect the vital interest ob- jectives of the Communist powers, then it would become clear to them also that the Cold War had its roots in Soviet ambition and intransigence. Such a display of genuine concern for arriving at arrangements which would protect the vital in- terests of the Soviet bloc countries would inspire more serious thought about the nature of Soviet objectives, thought which at once would be more serious and more critical of those objectives. I am convinced that such an approach by the United States would face the Soviet leaders with the neces- sity of defending what is really indefensible, and that is their expansionist ambitions. I am convinced that with such an approach we would at one and the same time greatly increase our prestige in the non-Soviet areas of the world and put increasing pressure upon the Soviets to take a much more reasonable approach themselves. Now at this point it may be objected that this is nothing more than the old game of power politics. The objection is to the point. I would, however, defend myself, and power politics, on two counts. First, I would insist that I am talking about power politics with a conscience; a conscience which is sensitive to the vital interests of other nations as well as to those of one’s own nation. I have the concept of vital national interests rather than the bare concept of national interest because it seems to me there is an important ethical difference between the two. Mr. Webster suggests that a suitable synonym for interest is advantage. If we pursue a policy dedicated to maximizing the national advantage in all situa- tions, with no thought as to the impact of our policy upon the vital interests of others, and with no at- tempt to limit our own objectives to those necessary for protection of national security and the integrity of our national way-of-life, if, in other words, we pursue a policy designed to serve the national in- terest in its narrowest meaning, we will be in the position of identifying any self-serving national be- hi tc nA co. havior as morally acceptable. To do so seems to me to deprive ethics of its key role as a factor limiting self-serving behavior. I do not mean to imply that a foreign policy con- ducted by a statesman whose conscience is sensitive to the vital interests of other nations is a foreign policy which is ethically perfect. I think there is al- ways an unbridgeable gap between the morally per- fect and desirable act, on the one hand, and the real and possible act on the other hand. Morally sensitive men live their lives in the tension created by this gap. In neither his private nor political role can man perform the totally good act; the best he can hope for is the wisdom, the moral sensitivity, and the courage to choose the least evil of the alternatives open to him. And in his foreign policy acts the statesman cannot forget that he acts not on his own behalf but rather on behalf of a nation of many people, a nation whose vital interests he is sworn to defend. He cannot forswear success for his own nation—defined in terms of the vital interests of that nation—in favor of a morally more satisfying but nationally disastrous course of action. I do not, therefore, mean to leave the impression that this approach to the ethical problem in foreign policy assures the peaceful solution of all problems among states. It clearly does not. Even if all of the world’s statesmen adopted this approach there would still surely be instances in which the vital interests of State A would conflict with the vital interests of State B. In such instances, victory would go to the more powerful and astute state. There would also still be instances in which the vital interests of two large powers could be protected only by sacrificing the interests of a smaller power—Korea and some of Py qe of Eastern Europe may well be examples My point is not that this approach dispels all of the tragedy of international affairs. Rather, my point is that such an approach provides a base from which we can understand the tragedy, and from which the morally sensitive statesman can judge the extent of his inevitable guilt. The second count on which I would defend my position on power politics can be more briefly put. I would claim that only power politics informed by conscience provides us with an approach to inter- national relations which maximizes the use we can make of such elements of social control as exist in international society, namely the reason and moral insight of statesmen. To discredit the need for ra- tional power calculations and for a conscientious recognition of the vital interests of all parties con- cerned in a headlong effort to save the world with grandiose schemes for world law, world government, world public opinion, or a codification of the moral law, is to ignore the problem and comfort ourselves with our own good thoughts. worldview 170 East 64th Street New York 21, N. Y. Check enclosed $ One Year $2.00 SUBSCRIPTION BLANK Please enter [] renew [] my subscription to worldview Name Address (Make checks payable to worldview) at d l- it )- d d re et re m d S- d id 1e ig re ‘is S. is as he he on or od a- cy at- ry ty ve in- he ye- 5 nuclear weapons RIGHT AND WRONG CALCULATION Paul Ramsey “Calculation is the life blood of politics,” writes Ernest W. Lefever, “and the heart of ethics” (“The Ethics of Calculation,” Worldview, October, italics added). This statement should be subjected to thorough scrutiny, and searchingly criticized. Indeed, calculation is the heart of ethics as Mr. Lefever understands it. For this reason, there is for him no particular difficulty about making ethico- litical judgements; and there is little to disturb or limit the “moral-political calculations” of which he speaks, since the heart of morality was already as- sumed to be calculative. Research the facts and weigh them tg wale this is about all that is needed in politics; and, happily, also about all it is the busi- ness of ethics to do. Of course, uniquely ethical terms are used at decisive points in this analysis; and they have to be understood and not dismissed for not playing an effective role. What is meant by the statement that “principles, goals and values are inescapably involved in all political decisions”? It seems clear in the context of the whole article that the words “prin- ciples” and “values” the same function and have the same place in relation to political decision and action as the word “goals.” Mr. Lefever writes that “no statesman can make policy from principles alone”; and this sentence is followed immediately by: “He must relate goals and ideals to the political facts of life.” It is not wrong to regard the second sentence as bearing a relation of “Hebrew paral- lelism” to the first; and to conclude that the word “principles” means the same as the words “goals” and “ideals.” We may reach the same conclusion from consider- ing Mr. Lefever’s assertion about George Kennan’s “disengagement” proposals: “They emerged from a rational attempt to relate facts to values, which cer- tainly included a calculation of the probable con- sequences of competing policies.” Here, it may be allowed, not all “consequences” are “values”; but still values are always only among the consequences, and there is no value (or moral “principle”) that is not among the consequences and therefore correctly related to action through calculation. A “principle” operates in this analysis of politics in the same way as a “value”; and a “value” means a “goal” or “ideal” —perhaps even a “dream.” Mr. Ramsey is Chairman of the Department of Religion in Princeton University. This means that, in Mr. Lefever’s opinion, ethics is wholly future-facing; and therefore, since nh i calculation is future-facing, ethics and political cal- culation go nicely together, and in fact calculation is the heart of ethics. Far from this being the case, we must affirm to the contrary that a wholly tele- ological view of ethics amounts to the suspension of ethics. This is the case whether our goals are spiritual or material, whether the ideals or values we seek are believed to be on earth or in heaven. If no more can be said about the morality of action than can be derived backward from the future goal, thus un- rolling toward the present the path that we shall have to tread by deeds determined by calculating their utility, ethics has already more half-way vanished, i.e., it has become calculation of the means to projected ends. Of course, these ends, goals, values toward which “moral-political calculation” is directed may them- selves be high and mighty important ones, and it does make a great deal of difference what are the goals or values a society seeks. Still, this is to sa at there is nothing that should not be done whi a future-facing calculation seems to require; and no action which can be calculated to produce the de- scribed result which should not therefore be defined as good. Such a view has to be rejected as the sus- pension of a great part of ethics, without in any sense minimizing the significance of calculation for both ethics and politics. Protestant Christian ethics today comes from a long line of prudent people. The pacifism which be- tween the world wars spread widely in the non- peace churches, the non-pacifism which bee. overcame this as World War II approached and which continues today, the increasing pragmatism of the Niebuhrians, the rejection of natural law and “middle axioms” in favor of contextualism and the study of “decision eae —all this has been largely a matter of determining the “lesser evil” or perchance the “greater good,” and, by a calculation of the facts, finding the path along which action should be directed in order to defend or secure some sort of values at the end of the road toward which action reaches, yet never reaches. This is an ethic well calculated to reduce every present reality—people and principles no less than facts—altogether to what they may do to bring in the future. Against this, it should be affirmed that “prudence” has rightly to be understood to be in the service of some prior principle, whether in application of natural law principles or (if, as I believe, these alone are in- adequate) in application of divine charity. No one can read the so-called Dun report of the Federal Council of Churches (“The Christian Con- science and Weapons of Mass Destruction”, Decem- les Ke nu ha sta ab ga ax ber, 1950) without fee the moral confusion beneath its weak rejection of “total” war. The “sense” in which total war was repudiated was there defined as “war in which all moral restraints are thrown aside and all the of the community are fully controlled by sheer military expedience”; and this clearly meant, in the main, wanton killing or a savagery that kills without reckoning: “We cannot, therefore, be released from the responsibility for doing no more hurt than must be.” In other words, the main consideration effective in this report was the sigue balancing of effects, of greater against evils. “ When prudence stands so nearly alone, and only in the context of a teleological ethic, it is not surpris- ing that for long stretches of the way, with the exception of a few unassimilated sentences about the moral immunity of non-combatants, this sounds rather like a statement of standards for the Housing, Care and Surgical Handling of Laboratory Animals. After all, in the latter case no one coun- tenances wanton cruelty, and the teleologically sus- pended ethics of the code of the S.P.C.A. is quite capable of ruling that it is “immoral” to use methods that cause laboratory rats more pain and maiming without commensurate medical or scientific decisive- ness. This outlook has not yet come upon any crucial moral considerations. Robert L. Calhoun, therefore, was quite correct when in his minority statement he wrote concernin: ng the majority opinion: “The norm of practically ef- fective inhibitions turns out to be, after all, military decisiveness; but beyond ruling out wanton destruc- Christian Ms time seems ve chiefly the effect ( inly important but scarcely decisive ) of making Christians do reluctantly what military necessity requires.” Not only a pacifist like Calhoun should be able to say this, but anyone from whose conscience the principles of the just war doctrine have not been completely eroded, as against mere future-facing calculation of consequences. The morality of means referred to in the “justified” war theory meant more than the inert weapon as such; it meant the conduct of war as such, the action as a whole and its nature, which had a morality or an immorality not wholly swallowed up in consequences or in motive to ends believed to justify any action that may be thought to have military decisiveness. Mr. Lefever’s reduction of ethics to calculation leaves him unable properly to understand George Kennan’s recent pronouncements on nuclear tests and nuclear weapons, and incapable of pointing out what has been correct and what mistaken in Kennan’s statements. He cites, for example, the latter’s remark about the danger from nuclear fallout: “Whoever gave us the right, as Christians, to take even one innocent life?” This, Mr. Lefever says, illustrates “Mr. Kennan’s nonchalant attitude toward facts and calculation in the area of nuclear weapons.” Actual- ly, this shows the one grave mistake Kennan has made in the use of ethical principles; and this needs to be corrected before Mr. Lefever or anyone else launches upon a calculation of the facts which K i to have r chalan pie is supposed refused, non tly The basic error in theoretical analysis is that in what he says about the future innocents who may die as a result of present tests, Mr. Kennan treats the probable effect of our present actions as if it were a means at present employed to obtain the ends we desire. The time-sequence of the acts put forth by men or nations cannot be reversed in fis way. action thrusts toward the future, and or most actions have double or multiple effects or consequences in the future; and this raises questions of a different order from the ethics of the means or the nature of the present action as such. Granted that the death of one child from man- made leukemia will be evil in itself, there is a significant distinction still to be made between whether this is an effect among many other good and evil effects that will result from our present course of action, or whether it is a means which, intentionally and in and of itself, objectively as well as subjectively, is ordered to the ro OE of some choice-worthy goal. While the end may never justify the means, one effect justifies another effect, in the sense that an evil, unavoidable effect may be produced if that is the only way, by action not wrong in itself, to secure some very good result. Now we come, and only at this point, do we come, to the proper work of cal- culation, in the comparison of effects, weighing their gravity, estimating the sufficiency of the reasons for them, and balancing greater against lesser goods or lesser evils. To no one Mr. Lefever will it seem that Kennan’s “implied judgment that all bomb tests under all circumstances are mo wrong seems to be based in part upon a picture of fallout danger that bears little resemblance to the findings of leading research institutions in this country and abroad. How can it seriously be ested that Kennan cal- culated, or miscalculated, his way to the absolute judgment about not taking one innocent life? If this was mistaken as applied to nuclear tests, it was a mistake in principle, in not distinguishing between taking human life as a means, and unavoidably taking human life as one of the indirect effects of action, to some good end. Presumably there will be a degree of genetic the cases of leukemia, to result from joint under- ground nuclear explosions, recently proposed by Mr. 7 Selwyn Lloyd, since a “negligible” amount of radia- tion will leak out Genaghe cracks in the mountain, but a possible result may also be a greater likelihood of agreement on banning future tests because the nations may learn how oe ae the instruments for detecting them. Mr. Lefever should say to Mr. Kennan: this good and that evil have to be calculated and weighed the one against the other; and your refusal to pay proper attention to the facts results from your failure to see that a possibly evil effect that may follow along with good effects from any action is not to be understood as an immoral means causally conducive to one of these other effects as an end. Then only will the ground in morality be made secure beneath Mr. Lefever’s own contentions: (1) “Genetic damage resulting from tests or general war or both, like the number of automobile deaths in the United States, is well within the range of what a civilized society is prepared to tolerate.” (2) “A policy designed to save ten thousand persons from possible future death by radioactivity which had the actual effect of inviting the death of ten million persons today could hardly be called morally re- sponsible or politically wise.” No one should wince at these statements, provided it is clear that a society engaging in these calcula- tions as to the indirect effects of action would already have become uncivilized if it engages at all in a like calculation at another point, ie., if it might under certain circumstances be persuaded that the life of one or the lives of ten or ten thousand may be directly repressed simply as a means that good may come of it. But Mr. Lefever jumps altogether over the mo- rality of action when at another point he becomes absorbed in calculations—calculation which is always only a subordinate part of moral judgment and to be entered upon logically only after the ethical guide- lines of action have been fixed. “According to the best projections available,” he writes, “the maximum beard re loss of life from a general nuclear war involving the full present capacities of the Soviet Union and the United States would be about twenty percent of the earth’s population. The number killed might well be considerably less. There would be practically no casualties of any kind south of the equator . . . If calculations of those in the best posi- tion to know are reasonably accurate, the worst nuclear war possible now would leave eighty per- cent of the earth’s population alive and healthy.” It is not that this calculation in the case of nuclear war, like David, has already killed its ten thousands, while calculation in the case of nuclear testing, like Saul, has already killed only its thousands. At its heart, ethics counts not in quantities and, as Kant said, you cannot do morality a greater disservice than by deriving it from ience. It is rather that the death and devastation contemplated in the case of all-out nuclear war would be both direct willed and directly done as a means, while the dea brought about by nuclear testing as such is only indirectly willed and indirectly done as one among several effects of the tests. The first is murder, the second tragic. In the one case, death to the innocent is the instrument used for defense or victory; in the other case, death to the innocent is a foreknown side-effect of action done in such a way as may be judged to be good, or at least neutral, in itself, and to be necessary to obtain great good results. The latter calculation concerning nuclear tests may be wrong; but in the former case it would be wrong to calculate and count on the good or less evil consequences that may come from a wrong done (acts of all-out nuclear war). The recent utterances of George Kennan have all been, not calls to abandon calculation, but to abandon calculation in the wrong place, in the place of fundamental moral principle. He has tried to recall us to the only doctrine of civilized warfare the West has known, to a reexamination as a “straight issue of conscience” of the degree of acceptance of in- discriminate bombing by nuclear weapons that is present in our nuclear deterrence policy, and to call us back from our apparent willingness to rest our security (as he said recently to the Women’s Demo- cratic Club in Washington, D.C.) on weapons de- i to “destroy innocent noncombatant human ife, including the lives of children, on a vast scale,” back from “an infinitely costly and hopeless exercise in reciprocal menace” by means which it would be vastly immoral ever to use. There can be no greater evil, I take Kennan to be saying, than the act of using unlimited weapons all- out; and the one thing worse than to suffer such an evil would be to do it. Sophistry has always opposed a Gorgias who declares this to be the case. Kennan is quite right, no calculation taught him this, nor should calculation be allowed to deprive him or us of a forever valid moral judgment. It is interesting that at one point Mr. Lefever speaks of the lack of statesmanlike utility to be found in “Mr. Kennan’s manners and principles.” It is very true that the latter’s principles, like his “sheer good manners,” would be falsified and dis- pelled if either were sought to be leveled to the one dimension of their future-facing consequences. Good manners like good morals are never qualities wholly teleologically oriented or derived; and while calcula- tion is of servite to both, it cannot be the heart of either. Manners and morals have, in different ways, to do with the definition of right conduct and not e ‘ q ‘ & n BPP Rees only with the ends of action; with the how and not only with what we do or the whither of our deeds. Mr. Kennan has not confused manners with morals or manners with policy, as Mr. Lefever as- serts, unless the substance of policy and of morals is supposed to embrace only “moral-political calcula- tion” and to be exhausted in their teleological refer- ence to the goals of action. It is altogether praise- worthy that Kennan has emphasized that the prin- ciples of political conduct, or the conduct of politics, overn action as such in more ways than is required 2 a calculative utility. It is good also that Kennan, experienced as he is the practice of diplomacy, as- sures amateurs who are apt to believe such prin- ciples to be reeds shaken by every wind that blows from over our future goals, and apt also, as outsiders to affairs of state, to believe realistic calculation af- fords a greater surety and a clearer direction, that a statesman’s “farsightedness and powers of calcula- tion” alone may often not be worth relying on. He calls us neither to policies guided only by principles without calculation (as do some neo-pacifists) nor (as do many of his critics) to policies guided only Aa calculation and doubtfully controlled by “ideals.” In this sense, Mr. Lefever, not Mr. Kennan, is the “idealist” in politics. The idealist is one who goes on his way and finds his way under the lure of such goals as the greatest good of the greatest number, etc. A realist is one who knows that there are many ways that reasonably may be supposed to lead there, ranging all the way from the noblest to the most wicked political decisions and actions; and he reminds the calculative idealist that in politics he had better know more than this about right and wrong conduct. We shall have to know more than this if mankind in the state of modern civilization is going to make it around the next turn. Those who say that it may not be possible for us to limit warfare are almost certainly correct. Surely war will never be kept a just endurable human enterprise if it is sought to kept limited only “by political objectives, and therefore limited in terms of the weapons employed,” and if fear alone is invoked to restrain the means. Limited ends do tend to moderate the means ven- tured and caused to be mounted in return, and the cost paid and exacted in warfare. But not only the military force made possible by modern technology works against our being able to achieve the control of warfare by aiming at modest ends, but also the endless restless aspiration of the human spirit, which displays its want of heaven even in the towering attempts at grandeur and wick- edness with which history is replete. Moreover, ends and means int etrate; and this can be as well read in the other direction: limited (or unlimited) means or weapons are available and resolved to be used, and therefore limited (or unlimited) political objectives may be thought to be proper goals in war. Calculative morality and politics cannot dis- pene with exhortations to people to adopt only imited goals, and therefore it must rely upon a revival of this aspect of the moral tradition of civilized warfare. At the same time there is need for a re-creation, in both thought and feeling, of the moral tradition of civilized warfare as to the right conduct of war and the moral limitation to be placed upon means. Surely, the immunity of noncombatants from in- discriminate, direct attack may come again to gov- ern the consciences of men as readily or with as great improbability as they will set limits to the political objectives they pursue. nee It would ill behoove churchmen, in this land that so dramatically overstepped this moral limit, not to follow the lead Mr. Kennan has given. For, rightly understood, his is not a rejection of calcula- tion in its proper place, nor a neo-pacifism based on a new religious absolutism inserted into politics where it is alien, but a reconstruction of the ancient theory of “justified” warfare, which always supposed that war for the wrong ends and war conducted contrary to the natural (rational) law of war as a just barely human enterprise (however immoral means may be calculated to be required by political objectives) was not so to be engaged in by either just or good Christian men. outstanding pamphlets in The Church Peace Union’s publications series. Quantity rates available upon request. (1 MORALITY AND MODERN WAR by John Courtney Murray, S.J. 23 pages 25 cents (] ETHICS AND NATIONAL PURPOSE by Kenneth W. Thompson 26 pages 25 cents RELIGION AND INTERNATIONAL RESPONSIBILITY by Robert Gordis 21 pages 25 cents | ‘ ve yer be his lis- me od lly la- of ys; ‘ot On Rendering to Caesar and to God How to Serve God in a Marxist Land by Karl Barth and Johannes Hamel. Association Press. 126 pp. $2.50. Communism and the Theologi- ans: Study of an Encounter by Charles C. West. Westminster Press. 399 pp. $6.00 by Roger L. Shinn Recently, Western religion has sometimes labored conscientiously for peace; it has also led to im- placable opposition to Soviet pow- er. Occasionally, it has seemed that the most religious people were the least willing to see any — in negotiation or in peace- resolution of difficulties. In this lexing situation two books throw new light upon the Christian understanding of Com- munism in a variety of situations. Both, at the very least, confront American Christians with views radically different from the con- ventional ones in our own society. A well-publicized letter of Karl Barth, written in August, 1958, to answer some questions from an East German pastor, gives the occasion for the first book. Ameri- can readers, finding a few of Barth’s more sensational state- ments in the press, wondered whether he was drawing closer to Communism. Now that the entire letter is available in English, Barth's thought appears to be about the same as in many oc- casional utterances since the sec- ond World War. Barth can be annoying enough. He dismisses a challenge as dis- honest without answering it or looking for its meaning. He gives advice on a loyalty oath which he has never read. He comments caustically about subjects on which he has not bothered to get information. And he treats glibly Christians who try to live faith- Mr. Shinn is a member of the faculty of the Union Theological Seminary in New York City. 10 fully with painful responsibilities which Barth and the Eastern astors, quite properly, do not ve. Yet, when that is said, it re- mains true that European pastors have responsibilities which we may fail to appreciate. For Amer- ican churchmen to neglect their opportunity to influence foreign policy would be a shameful re- treat. East German Christians do not have that responsibility; for them to concentrate on it would be irrelevant daydreaming. They do have a dangerous ministry, which some of them exercise courageously in the midst of frustrations that would destroy any conventional faith. When Barth tells them the ' Biblical message about faith in times of ecution, he writes meaningfully for any Christian. He speaks profoundly about the Christian’s relation to atheists: “You must meet their unbelief with a joyous unbelief in their attempted atheism. You as Chris- tians must confidently claim that your atheists belong to God as much as you do.” Actually, Barth, despite many sentences which imply the con- trary, says plainly that he dis- approves Soviet practices “just as much” as he disapproves “the pow- ers and dominions that rule over us here in the West.” Elsewhere he has expressed a Christian pref- erence for “civil communities of free peoples.” But he is reluctant to say so now, lest he feed the fires of anti-Communism. The West, he thinks, is too likely to succumb to insidious temptations just because it sees Communism as the main threat. On that point Barth is unquestionably right. He might be surprised to know that American preaching frequently says the same thing. In the same volume with Barth’s letter is an essay, “The Proclama- tion of the Gospel in the Marxist World,” by Johannes Hamel, a pastor in East Germany. Writing in terms of a Barthian theology, he speaks out of vivid and dan- erous experience. He answers efeatism and despair by show- ing that the rer which trusts in Christ’s victory can always un- dertake its mission in confidence. He sees in Communism (as Isaiah saw in the ians) the “rod of God’s anger” against the in- justices of Western society; he acknowledges a validity of Com- munist government; and he looks for every opportunity to proclaim the Gospel and exercise its heal- ing ministry. An American, who might disagree at points, is more likely to be silenced by admira- tion for Christian courage. When Hamel extends his im- mediate testimony into broader theories of history and politics, he is on shakier ground. He comes dangerously close to the notion of the “wave of the future,” which accepts any powerful historical movement as somehow God's work, which should not be op- posed or reshaped. This is not to question Hamel’s vocation of ministering within the Communist regime; it is only to assert that other Christians—perhaps Bishop Dibelius or Chancellor Adenauer —can find their vocations in per- sistent Scriptural themes which Hamel does not use. Charles West’s massive study of Communism and the Theolo- gians raises similar issues in vastly different style and scope. Instead of the occasional writings by Barth and Hamel, he produces a thorough scholarly analysis of re- lations between Communism and Christianity, both in the lives of people and in the writings of eminent Christian thinkers. West raises questions for any Christian response to Communism —questions which are likely to | 6 TPS GT arr SRAESSYV SREB ALA? be humbling to us in the West, who usually face Communism only in terms of a power struggle. Does Christian t answer adequately the Marxist challenge that it is the ideology of the com- fortable? Does Christianity show appreciation for the revolutionary ferment of our time, and can it compare with Marxism in urgency and direction to A gy social change? Does the Christian know how to use power, and how to use powerlessness and suffer- ing in today’s world? How does the Christian exercise his ministry to the Communist as a person? West (unlike some of the theo- logians he studies) is convinced that resistance to Communism’s tyrannical power is necessary. But resistance is an incomplete answer. For we live in a revolu- tionary age. Communism is an oc- casion for Christian repentance and a prod to Christian revolu- tionary activity. In examining the many types of Christian confrontation with Com- munism, West deliberately omits the obsolete attempts of a left- wing Social Gospel to bring Chris- tianity and Communism together. He concentrates on thoroughly contemporary materials. Here he discerns, first, those Christians who identify Communism simply as the enemy. The chief of these is Emil Brunner, but West also mentions John Foster Dulles, Charles Lowry, and Whittaker Chambers. At the opposite end of the spectrum are those who, without confusing Communism with the Christian revelation, nevertheless see in Communism the nemesis of an out-moded civilization and the creator of a new society in which the Church must live. Among these West in- cludes Josef Hromadka and Bish- op Berecsky. In both these extreme views West generously acknowledges elements of truth. But his verdict is a smashing rejection. In another position, which rec- ognizes the Western failures that prompt the Communist protest, yet sees all the evils in Commu- nism, West finds wisdom and realism. Within this area he looks at Tillich and Berdyaev, whom he appreciates but refutes. Then he concentrates on Reinhold Niebuhr and Karl Barth. Toward these men he shows great admiration and affection, yet launches search- ing criticisms. In Niebuhr, West finds “the sharpest analyst of world Com- munist power and of Christian responsibility in the face of it.” Niebuhr above all others brings together “the way of love revealed in Christ” and “the problems of responsible social action.” But, tracing Niebuhr’s shift from early social radicalism to increasing pragmatism and _ conservatism, West sees the danger of ideologi- cal thinking. For Niebuhr, rely- ing more and more on the im- portance of a heritage of Ameri- can values, sees Communism as a threat to a good social order, and misses its powerful appeal to those in the midst of social chaos. From West's description one might never guess that Niebuhr’s writings have asked, in all seri- ousness, whether East Germany provides a more favorable en- vironment for Christianity than America. Nor would one realize that Niebuhr has written penetrat- ing comments on the problems, both international and domestic, of our economy of abundance. But all of us who enjoy Ameri- can security and prosperity must admit vulnerability to West's charge that we too easily acqui- esce in our present way of life. In Karl Barth, West finds the hal contempo: theology which best Christian faith and most powerfully con- fronts Communism. Yet he finds Barth poorly in- formed about Communism Pong ilty of “ineptitude” in politics. od Barth's judgments about Communism are ca y mistaken. In this area West wishes that Barth might: learn from Niebuhr. West himself turns to Helmut Gollwitzer and Dietrich Bonhoeffer to improve upon Barth. This discussion of Barth’s theo- logy has some logical flaws. West works laboriously but futiley to show that this theology has a built-in guarantee against ideolo- gical bias, because it derives so exclusively from Jesus Christ. But theology works from some human conception of Christ, which may be tragically ideological. It is at least possible that Barth’s rather easy assumption of the victory = Christ on evil is the ground r an ideology of irresponsibility, quite a Swiss thinkee who need not participate in the major —— struggles of our time. Although West shows the powerful nature of ideology, he does not quite see its full danger to all of us. Another difficulty comes in West's abstraction of theology from human decisions. He con- stantly talks about Barth’s ey theology which is badly “applied” to the world of political affairs. This notion of theology as some- thing to be fully developed, then applied, is a curious one. One might ask whether theology does not spring out of the address of the living Word of God to actual situations, in such a way that the so-called application is scarcely necessary because it has entered into the very meaning of —e Finally, West, prompted by love for both Barth and Niebuhr, wants to show that the two are closer together than most people think. But his attempt has con- vinced one reader that they are farther apart than West or most people think. These criticisms refer to the abstract parts of West's arguments. When he deals with the concrete confrontation of Christianity and Communism, he has brilliant perceptiveness and powerful insight. Any American can learn a great deal from this ll er- ich \dy by sa re- and ; of any ism to current reading Soviet Policy Toward the Baltic States, 1918-1940 by Albert N. Tarulis. University of Notre Dame Press. 276 pp. $5.50. The lost countries of the Baltic—Estonia, Latvia and Lithuania— are a frequently neglected chapter in the history of Soviet im- perialism. Dr. Tarulis, a native of Lithuania who witnessed the Russian occupation, now tells the story in a thoroughly documented version which dates the beginnings of annexation back to "the Bolshevik duplicity" of 1918. Triumph in the West by Arthur Bryant. Doubleday. 438 pp. $6.95. The second and concluding volume to be based on the personal diaries of Field-Marshall Lord Alanbrooke covers the crucial months between 1943 and 1946 and provides a provocative in- sight into first-level strategy decisions and the men who made them. The Riddie of Roman Catholicism by Jaroslav Pelikan. Abingdon. 272 pp. $4.00. Written mainly for Protestants by a Protestant, this study displays an intimate knowledge of the Catholic Church's history, structure and doctrines, and can be read with profit by persons of all faiths who seek an understanding of “the most formidable religi- ous institution in the history of America and the world." Controls for Outer Space by Philip C. Jessup and Howard J. Taubenfeld. Columbia Univer- sity Press. 379 pp. $6.00. Citing as precedents the various types of experimental interna- tional cooperation that have been developed in the past either by sovereign states or under the aegis of the League of Nations or the UN, the authors advance a series of proposals for similar international administration of Antarctica and the province of outer space. Issues and Conflicts Edited by George L. Anderson. University of Kansas Press. 374 pp. $5.00. In a collection of essays, a number of American scholars and historians examine the effects of twentieth century American diplomacy on China, the Middle East, Asian nationalism, im- migrant groups, Latin America and Germany. Too Many Asians by John Robbins. Doubleday. 214 pp. $3.95. Malthus’ prophecy is bearing bitter fruit today in Asia, where unprecedented growth in population now threatens the lives and welfare of over half the world's inhabitants and raises grave and immediate problems for the relatively secure West. This. report provides an analysis of the population explosion, with particular emphasis on China, India and Japan. worldview A JOURNAL OF RELIGION AND INTERNATIONAL AFFAIRS volume 2, n0o.12 / December 1959 WORLDVIEW is published monthly by The Church Peace Union. Subscription: $2.00 per year. Address: 170 East 64th Street, New York 21, N. Y. EDITORIAL BOARD William Clancy, Editor 4. William Loos William J. Cook John R. Inman Editorial Assistant, Arlene Croce CONTENTS Editorial made In the Magazines... The Power to Negotiate. E. Raymond Platig Right and Wrong Calculation............ Paul Ramsey BOOKS God and Caesar by Roger L. Shinn.........-. Opinions expressed in WORLDVIEW are and met necessarily of The Church Worldview 170 East 64th Street New York 21, N. Y. an me 5 ‘ é | |